Who is mead sociology




















The past, which by definition can only exist in the present, changes to accommodate novel events. It is certainly the case that if one were to emphasize Mead's concern with social systems and the social development of the self, one might be led to conclude that Mead is a theorist of the processes of socialization. And the latter, nested as they are within social systems, are beyond the control of individuals.

But his emphasis on novelty only seems to counter determinism with spontaneity. This counter to determinism in itself doesn't supply a notion of autonomy—self-governance and self-determination—which is often viewed as crucial to the modern Western notion of the subject.

However, Mead was a firm booster of the scientific method, which he viewed as an activity that was at its heart democratic. For him, science is tied to the manner in which human beings have managed from pre-recorded times to solve problems and transform their worlds. We have just learned to be more methodical about the ways in which we solve problems in modern science.

Life and Influences 2. Language and Mind 3. Roles, the Self, and the Generalized Other 4. Sociality, Emergence, and The Philosophy of the Present 6. I shall have to let persons understand that I have some belief in Christianity and my praying be interpreted as a belief in God, whereas I have no doubt that now the most reasonable system of the universe can be formed to myself without a God. But notwithstanding all this I cannot go out with the world and not work for men.

The spirit of a minister is strong with me and I come fairly by it. Shalin , — Mead did indeed move away from his earlier religious roots, but the activist spirit remained with him.

Language and Mind Dewey and Mead were not only very close friends, they shared similar intellectual trajectories. MSS, — It is by means of reflexiveness—the turning back of the experience of the individual upon himself—that the whole social process is thus brought into the experience of the individuals involved in it; it is by such means, which enable the individual to take the attitude of the other toward himself, that the individual is able consciously to adjust himself to that process, and to modify the resultant of that process in any given social act in terms of his adjustment to it.

MSS, Mind is developed not only through the use of vocal gestures, but through the taking of roles, which will be addressed below. Actual experience did not take place in this form but in the form of unsophisticated reality. MSS, — 3. Roles, the Self, and the Generalized Other One of the most noteworthy features of Mead's account of the significant symbol is that it assumes that anticipatory experiences are fundamental to the development of language. Thus, for example, in the case of such a social group as a ball team, the team is the generalized other in so far as it enters—as an organized process or social activity—into the experience of any one of the individual members of it.

MSS, For Mead, although these communities can take different forms, they should be thought of as systems; for example, a family can be thought of systemically and can therefore give rise to a generalized other and a self that corresponds to it. Generalized others can also be found in concrete social classes or subgroups, such as political parties, clubs, corporations, which are all actually functional social units, in terms of which their individual members are directly related to one another.

The others are abstract social classes or subgroups, such as the class of debtors and the class of creditors, in terms of which their individual members are related to one another only more or less indirectly. MSS, In his Principles of Psychology , a book Mead knew well, William James discusses various types of empirical selves, namely, the material, the social, and the spiritual.

Properly speaking , a man has as many social selves as there are individuals who recognize him and carry an image of him in their mind.

To wound any one of these his images is to wound him. But as the individuals who carry the images fall naturally into classes, we may practically say that he has as many different social selves as there are distinct groups of persons about whose opinion he cares.

He generally shows a different side of himself to each of these different groups. James , From Mead's vantage point, James was on the right track.

It seems to me that the extreme mathematization of recent science in which the reality of motion is reduced to equations in which change disappears in an identity, and in which space and time disappear in a four dimensional continuum of indistinguishable events which is neither space nor time is a reflection of the treatment of time as passage without becoming.

PP, 19 The universe doesn't just spin its wheels and offer motion without real novelty. In the words of David Miller, According to Mead, every perspective is a consequence of an active, selecting organism, and no perspective can be built up out of visual experiences alone or out of experiences of the so-called secondary qualities.

A perspective arises out of a relation of an active, selective, percipient event and its environment. It determines the order of things in the environment that are selected, and it is in nature…. We make distinctions among objects in our environment, finally, through, contact. Miller , Mead has been referred to as a tactile philosopher, as opposed to a visual one, because of the importance of contact experience in his thought. When the new form has established its citizenship the botanist can exhibit the mutual adjustments that have taken place.

The world has become a different world because of the advent, but to identify sociality with this result is to identify it with system merely. It is rather the stage betwixt and between the old system and the new one that I am referring to. If emergence is a feature of reality this phase of adjustment, which comes between the ordered universe before the emergent has arisen and that after it has come to terms with the newcomer, must be a feature also of reality.

PP, 47 Sociality is a key idea for Mead and it has implications for his sociology and social psychology. To leave the field to the values represented by the old self is exactly what we term selfishness. The justification for the term is found in the habitual character of conduct with reference to these values. SS in SW, [emphasis added] It's worth noting here that Mead did not develop an ethics, at least not one that was systematically presented. The emergent when it appears is always found to follow from the past, but before it appears it does not, by definition, follow from the past.

PP, 2 6. Bibliography Primary Sources Abbreviations are noted for cited primary texts. Page references are to the reprinted edition in [SW] below. Morris, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, Morris, annotated by Daniel R. Moore, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, Andrew J. Reck, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, The Philosophy of Education , eds. Gert J. Baldwin, John D. Burke, F. Thomas and Krzysztof P. Cook, Gary A.

Arthur E. Peirce Society , 44 3 : — Gillespie, A. II , tr. Huebner, Daniel R. Reprinted, New York: Dover Publications, Reprint and the original have the same pagination. Page reference is to the reprinted edition in The Writings of William James , ed.

John J. Mead: A Contemporary Re-examination of his Thought , trs. Martin, Jack, and Gillespie, A. Martin, J. Page references are to the reprinted edition, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, Mead , Introduction by Horace M. Kallen, Washington, D. Pfuetze, Paul E. Stone, J. Rigney, Ernest G. Rosenthal, Sandra B. Academic Tools How to cite this entry.

Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database. Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative. Mirror Sites View this site from another server:. Selected Writings: George Herbert Mead , ed. Thus, objectivity can have meaning only within the domain of the subject, the realm of consciousness.

It is not that the existence of the objective world is constituted by consciousness, but that the meaning of that world is so constituted. In Husserlian language, the existence of the objective world is transcendent , i. History is founded on human action in response to emergent events.

Action is an attempt to adjust to changes that emerge in experience; the telos of the act is the re-establishment of a sundered continuity. Since the past is instrumental in the re-establishment of continuity, the adjustment to the emergent requires the creation of history. And the future- orientation of history entails that every new discovery, every new project, will alter our picture of the past.

Although Mead discounts the possibility of a transcendent past that is, a past independent of any present , he does not deny the possibility of validity in historical accounts.

An historical account will be valid or correct, not absolutely, but in relation to a specific emergent context. Historical thought is valid in so far as it renders change intelligible and permits the continuation of activity. An appeal to an absolutely correct account of the past is not only impossible, but also irrelevant to the actual conduct of historical inquiry.

A meaningful past is a usable past. Historians are, to be sure, concerned with the truth of historical accounts, i. The historical conscience seeks to reconstruct the past on the basis of evidence and to present an accurate interpretation of the data of history. Thus, for Mead, historical inquiry is the imaginative-but-honest, intelligent-and-intelligible reconstruction and interpretation of the human past on the basis of all available and relevant evidence.

But what is the ontological status of emergence? What is its relation to the general structure of reality? Nature is a system of systems or relationships; it is not a collection of particles or fragments which are actually separate. Distinctions, for Mead, are abstractions within fields of activity; and all natural objects animate or inanimate exist within systems apart from which the existence of the objects themselves is unthinkable.

The inside of the object, moreover, is not a projection from the organism, but is there in the relation between the organism and thing see The Philosophy of the Present , , The relation between organism and object, then, is a social relation The Philosophy of the Act Thus, the relation between a natural object or event and the system within which it exists is not unidirectional.

The character of the object, on the one hand, is determined by its membership in a system; but, on the other hand, the character of the system is determined by the activity of the object or event. There is a mutual determination of object and system, organism and environment, percipient event and consentient set The Philosophy of the Act While this mutuality of individual and system is characteristic of all natural processes, Mead is particularly concerned with the biological realm and lays great emphasis on the interdependence and interaction of organism and environment.

Whereas the environment provides the conditions within which the acts of the organism emerge as possibilities, it is the activity of the organism that transforms the character of the environment.

The relation of organism and environment is not static, but dynamic. The activities of the environment alter the organism, and the activities of the organism alter the environment.

The organism-environment relation is, moreover, complex rather than simple. The ability of the organism to act with reference to a multiplicity of situations is an example of the sociality of natural events.

By moving from one system to another, the organism confronts unfamiliar and unexpected situations which, because of their novelty, constitute problems of adjustment for the organism. These emergent situations are possible given the multiplicity of natural processes and given the ability of natural events e. A bee, for example, is capable of relating to other bees, to flowers, to bears, to little boys, albeit with various attitudes. But sociality is not restricted to animate events. A mountain may be simultaneously an aspect of geography, part of a landscape, an object of religious veneration, the dialectical pole of a valley, and so forth.

The capacity of sociality is a universal character of nature. The object is social, not merely in terms of its temporal relations, but also in terms of its relations with other objects in an instantaneous field. This mode of sociality constitutes the emergent event; that is, the state of a system at a given instant is the social reality within which emergent events occur, and it is this reality that must be adjusted to the exigencies of time.

It is on the basis of such socio-symbolic interactions between individuals, and by means of the conceptual symbols of the communicational process, that the mind and the self come into existence. The human world is also temporally structured, and the temporality of experience, Mead argues, is a flow that is primarily present. The past is part of my experience now , and the projected future is also part of my experience now. There is hardly a moment when, turning to the temporality of my life, I do not find myself existing in the now.

Thus, it would appear that whatever is for me, is now ; and, needless to say, whatever is of importance or whatever is meaningful for me, is of importance or is meaningful now. Our past is always with us in the form of memory, history, tradition, etc. The human present opens toward the future. The individual experiences himself as having choices, or as being confronted with situations which require choices on his part. He does not ordinarily experience himself as being controlled by the world.

The world presents obstacles to him, and yet he experiences himself as being able to respond to these obstacles in a variety even though a finite variety of ways. I am a being that exists in relation to a world. Freedom denied on one level of experience is rediscovered at another.

One must lose oneself in order to find oneself. A perspective, then, is a situation in which a percipient event or individual exists with reference to a consentient set or environment and in which a consentient set exists with reference to a percipient event.

There are, obviously, many such situations or perspectives. For Mead, perceptual objects arise within the act and are instrumental in the consummation of the act. Distance experience implies contact experience.

Perception leads on to manipulation. A terminal attitude, then, is an implicit manipulation of a distant object; it stands at the beginning of the act and is an intellectual-and-emotional posture in terms of which the individual encounters the world. As present in the beginning of the act, the terminal attitude contains the later stages of the act in the sense that perception implies manipulation and in the sense that manipulation is aimed at the resolution of a problem.

In terminal attitudes, all stages of the act interpenetrate. For example, a distant shape is seen as being palpable, as having a certain size and weight, as having such and such a texture, and so forth.

In perception, the manipulatory area is extended, and the distant object becomes hypothetically a contact object. In immediate perceptual experience, the distant object is in the future.

Contact with the distant object is implicit, i. The contemporaneity of individual and distant object is an abstraction within the act. Prior to actual manipulation, the perceiving individual anticipates a variety of ways in which a given object might be manipulated. This implicit testing of alternative responses to the distant object is the essence of reflective conduct.

The actual futurity of the distant object is suspended, and the object is treated as though it were present in the manipulatory area. This reduction of futurity, we have seen, is instrumental in the reflective conduct of the acting individual. In perception, then, distant objects are reduced to the manipulatory area and become hypothetically contact objects.

Perception involves the assumption of contact qualities in the distant object. Galileo articulated the latter distinction as follows:. I feel myself impelled by the necessity, as soon as I conceive a piece of matter or corporeal substance, of conceiving that in its own nature it is bounded and figured in such and such a figure, that in relation to others it is either large or small, that it is in this or that place, in this or that time, that it is in motion or remains at rest.

Hence I think that these tastes, odours, colors, etc. The primary qualities number, position, extension, bulk, and so forth are there in the object, but the secondary qualities are subjective reactions to the object on the part of the sensitive organism. A serious breakdown in the theory of primary and secondary qualities appeared in the critical epistemology of George Berkeley. According to Berkeley, whatever we know of objects, we know on the basis of perception. The primary as well as the secondary qualities of objects are apprehended in sensation.

Moreover, primary qualities are never perceived except in conjunction with secondary qualities. In the exigencies of action, we have seen, there is a tendency on the part of the acting individual to reduce distant objects to the contact area. The contact characters of the object become the main focus within the act, while the distance characters are bracketed out that is, held in suspension or ignored for the time being.

In his opposition to outright environmental determinism, Mead points out that the sensitivity, selectivity, and organizational capacities of organisms are sources of the control of the environment by the form. On the human level, for example, we find the phenomenon of attention. The human being selects her stimuli and thereby organizes the field within which she acts.

Attention, then, is characterized by its selectivity and organizing tendency. It is not simply a set of passive senses played upon by the stimuli that come from without. Attention is the foundation of human intelligence; it is the capacity of attention that gives us control over our experience and conduct. Attention is one of the elements of human freedom. The relation between organism and environment is, in a word, inter active.

In other words, perceptual objects are perspectively determined, and perspectives are determined by perceiving individuals. Even when we consider only sense data, the object is clearly a function of the whole situation whose perspective is determined by the individual. There are peculiarities in the objects which depend upon the individual as an organism and the spatio-temporal position of the individual.

It is one of the important results of the modern doctrine of relativity that we are forced to recognize that we cannot account for these peculiarities by stating the individual in terms of his environment.

The Philosophy of the Act The perceiving individual cannot be explained in terms of the so-called external world, since that individual is a necessary condition of the appearance of that world.

Mead thus abandons, on the basis of his interpretation of relativity theory, the object of Newtonian physics. But in addition to denying the concrete existence of independent objects, he also denies the existence of the independent psyche. There is nothing subjective about perceptual experience.

If objects exist with reference to the perceiving individual, it is also true that the perceiving individual exists with reference to objects. The qualities of objects distance as well as contact qualities exist in the relation between the perceiving individual and the world. The so-called secondary sensuous qualities, therefore, are objectively present in the individual-world matrix; sensuous characters are there in a given perspective on reality.

In actual perceptual experience, the object is objectively present in relation to the individual. The cosmos is nature stratified into a multiplicity of perspectives, all of which are interrelated. Mead distinguishes two main types of perspective: 1 the perceptual perspective and 2 the reflective perspective.

A perceptual perspective is rooted in the space-time world in which action is unreflective. This is the world of immediate perceptual experience. A reflective perspective is a response to the world of perceptual perspectives. The perspectives of fig trees and wasps are, from the standpoint of the trees and wasps hypothetically considered , perceptually independent, except for certain points of intersection that is, actual contacts.

The world of reflective perspectives is the world of reflective thought and action, the world of distance experience and the world of scientific inquiry. It is within the reflective perspective that the hypothetical objects of the collapsed act arise. Corresponding to the two types of perspective outlined above are two attitudes toward the perceptual objects which arise in experience.

The world that is there a phrase Mead uses over and over again includes our own acts, our own bodies, and our own psychological responses to the things that emerge in our ongoing activity. Perceptual objects, in the world that is there , are what they appear to be in their relation to the perceiving individual.

This attitude corresponds to the reflective perspective. It is through reflective analysis of perceptual objects that scientific objects are constructed. Such objects, according to Mead, are hypothetical abstractions which arise in the scientific attempt to explain the world of immediate experience.

Scientific objects are not objects of experience. Science accounts for the perceptible in terms of the non- perceptible and often the im perceptible. There is a danger in the reflective analysis of the world that is there , namely, the reification of scientific objects and the subjectification of perceptual objects.

The scientific object, moreover, has ultimate reference to the perceptual world. The act of reflective analysis within which the scientific object arises presupposes the world that is there in perceptual experience. Scientific objects are abstractions within the reflective act and are, in effect, attempts to account for the objects of perceptual experience.

And it is to the world that is there that the scientist must go to confirm or disconfirm the hypothetical objects of scientific theory. Reflective analysis thus arises within and presupposes an unreflective world of immediate experience. A later reflection turns back upon it and endeavors to present the complete interrelationship between the world and the individual in terms of physical stimuli and biological mechanisms [scientific objects]; the actual experience did not take place in this [hypothetical] form but in the form of unsophisticated reality Mind, Self and Society , , emphasis added.

The world that is there is prior to the reflective world of scientific theory. His aim is to demonstrate the objective reality of the perceptual world. He does not, however, deny the reality of scientific objects. Scientific objects are hypothetical objects which are real in so far as they render the experiential world intelligible and controllable. Harold N. Scientific knowledge is not final, but hypothetical; and the reality of scientific objects is, therefore, hypothetical rather than absolute.

Reflective conduct takes place with reference to problems that emerge in the world that is there , and the construction of scientific objects is aimed at solving these problems. Problematic situations occur within the world that is there ; it is not the entire world of experience that becomes problematic, but only aspects of that world.

It is to this field of unquestioned reality that the scientist returns to test his reconstructed theory. History, according to Mead, is the collective time of the social act. Historical thought arises in response to emergent events crises, new situations, unexpected disruptions that are confronted in community life. In this manner, the present difficulty becomes intelligible, and the emergent discontinuity of experience is potentially resolvable. Historical thought is a reconstruction of a communal past in an attempt to understand the nature and significance of a communal present and a potential communal future.

Historical accounts are never final since historical thought continually restates the past in terms of newly emergent situations in a present that opens upon a future.

Human life is an ongoing process that is temporally structured. The notion of the world at an instant the knife-edge present is, according to Mead, an abstraction within the act which may be instrumental in the pursuit of consummation; but as a description of concrete experience, the knife-edge present is a specious present.

The specious present is not the actual present of ongoing experience. It is what has just happened, what is going on, what is just appearing in the future, that gives to our experience its peculiar character. It is never an experience just at an instant. Human experience is fundamentally dynamic, and human life is built on a temporal foundation. The emergent event is the foundation of novelty in experience. This novelty is characteristic, not only of the present, but also of the past and future.

The future, on the one hand, lies beyond the emergent present; and the novelty of the future takes the form of the unexpected. The emergent event creates a future that comes to us as a surprise. The past, on the other hand, must be reinterpreted in the light of the emergent event; the result of such reinterpretation is nothing less than a new past.

Consciousness of the past develops in response to emergent events that alter our sense of temporal relationships.

We find that each generation has a different history, that it is a part of the apparatus of each generation to reconstruct its history. A different Caesar crosses the Rubicon not only with each author but with each generation. That is, as we look back over the past, it is a different past.

The experience is something like that of a person climbing a mountain. As he looks back over the terrain he has covered, it presents a continually different picture. So the past is continually changing as we look at it from the point of view of different authors, different generations. It is not simply the future [and present] which is novel, then; the past is also novel Movements of Thought in the Nineteenth Century History is the reconstruction of the past in response to a new present that opens toward a new future.

Science, according to Mead, thrives on novelty. Scientific inquiry is, in essence, a response to exceptions to laws. Scientific inquiry arises out of the conflict between what was expected to happen and what actually happens; contradictions in experience are the starting- points for the scientific reconstruction of knowledge Mead, Selected Writings Science, for Mead, is a continual reconstruction of our conception of the world in response to novel situations.

Science is a form of human existence, a way of moving with the changes that emerge before us. History is the science of the human past. But the historical past, as we have seen, is not independent of present and future. Historical inquiry, like scientific inquiry in general, takes place in a present that has become problematic through the occurrence of an emergent event. An ancient village is unearthed in Asia Minor, and the rise of human civilization is suddenly pushed back five thousand years in time; the demand on the part of African-Americans for liberty and identity leads to a revaluation of black culture in terms of its historical roots.

Historical thought reconstructs the past continually in an attempt to reveal the cognitive significance of present and future. It is not only the content of the past that is subject to change. Past events have meanings that are also changed as novel events emerge in ongoing experience.

The meaning of past events is determined by the relation of those events to a present. The elucidation of such meaning is the task of historical thought and inquiry. An historical account, as we have seen, is true to the extent that the present is rendered coherent by reference to past events.

Historical thought reinterprets the past in terms of the present. But this reinterpretation is not capricious. The historical past arises in the reexamination and representation of evidence. Historical accounts must be documented. No historical account, however, is final. The meaning of the past is always open to question; any given interpretation of the past may be criticized from the standpoint of a different interpretation.

The meaning of the past changes as present slides into present The Philosophy of the Present 9 and as different individuals and groups are confronted with new situations that demand a temporal reintegration of experience.

A new present suggests a new future and demands a new past. This interdependence of past, present, and future is the essential character of human temporality and of historical consciousness. In Movements of Thought in the Nineteenth Century , Mead offers the Romantic movement of the late 18th and 19th centuries as an example of the present and future orientation of human inquiries into the past. The Romantic historians and philosophers, confronted with the disruption of experience, which was the result of the early modern revolutionary period, turned to the medieval past in an effort to redefine the historical and cultural identity of European man.

The major characteristic of Romantic thought, according to Mead, was an attempt to redefine European self- consciousness through the re-appropriation of the historical past. The European had been cut off from his past by the political and cultural revolutions of the 16th, 17th, and 18th centuries; and in the post-revolutionary world of the early 19th century, the Romantic movement represented the European quest for a reconstructed identity.

It was history that provided the basis for this reconstruction. The idea of rationality has played a central role in modern social theory. Thus, the aim of modern social theory has been to root social institutions in human nature rather than in divine providence. The doctrine of the rights of man and the idea of the social contract, for example, were brought together by Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau in an effort to ground political order in a purely human world. Society was conceived as a voluntary association of individuals; and the aim of this association was the preservation of natural rights to such goods as life, liberty, and property.

Social authority, then, was derived from the individuals who had contracted to live together and to pursue certain human goals. This analysis of society was at the root of the revolutionary social criticism of the eighteenth century. When men came to conceive the order of society as flowing from the rational character of society itself; when they came to criticize institutions from the point of view of their immediate function in preserving order, and criticized that order from the point of view of its purpose and function; when they approached the study of the state from the point of view of political science; then, of course, they found themselves in opposition to the medieval attitude which accepted its institutions as given by God to the church Movements of Thought in the Nineteenth Century The institutions of the medieval past e.

But the new regime contained reactionary elements of its own. The victorious bourgeoisie began to build a new class society based on the dialectic of capital and labor; and in this new society, the rights of man came to be conceived in terms of the successful struggle for economic power Movements of Thought in the Nineteenth Century The initial effects of the rise of capitalist society were disastrous for the working classes.

It was only after the subsequent rise of the trade union and socialist movements that the contradiction between ideology and reality began to be transcended. The ideals of liberty, equality, and fraternity proved inadequate as bases for a fully rational society. In the actual political world, where there is a conflict of wills, the concept of freedom falls into contradiction with itself. The freedom of one individual or group often infringes upon the freedom of another individual or group Movements of Thought in the Nineteenth Century According to Mead, any society is a complex organization of many individuals and groups.

These individuals and groups possess varying degrees of power and prestige. Given this situation, the concept of equality is at most an ideal to be pursued; but it is not a description of what goes on the in the concrete social world. He was caught between two worlds. He could not be sure of his identity. His sense of self was in crisis. The Romantic movement was an attempt to overcome this crisis by returning to and reconstructing the European past. Romanticism, then, was an effort to reestablish the continuity between the past, present, and future of European culture.

The Romantic self, however, was not conceived of as transcendental. The Romantics agreed with Kant that the self is the basis of all knowledge and judgment. But while the Kantian self had been developed as a regulative concept in the attempt to render experience intelligible, the Romantic self was held to be actually constitutive of experience. That is what we insist upon. That is what gives the standard to values. Thus, for the Romantics, knowledge of the self was not only possible, but was viewed as the highest form of knowledge.

At the heart of the Romantic preoccupation with self-consciousness was the question of the relation between subject and object. It had even torn to pieces the philosophy of the Renaissance. Use precise geolocation data. Select personalised content. Create a personalised content profile. Measure ad performance. Select basic ads. Create a personalised ads profile. Select personalised ads. Apply market research to generate audience insights.

Measure content performance. Develop and improve products. List of Partners vendors. Share Flipboard Email. By Ashley Crossman. Updated August 20, Featured Video. Cite this Article Format. Crossman, Ashley. Biography of Sociologist George Herbert Mead.



0コメント

  • 1000 / 1000